Nick Hanauer asks a lot of the middle class

imageNick Hanauer’s TED talk—the one that apparently was “banned” (i.e., not immediately released on the TED site but available on YouTube)—makes the argument that middle class consumers, not businesses, create jobs.   Consumo ergo sum, as Fr. Robert Sirico describes the general attitude in his new book, Defending the Free Market: The Moral Case for a Free Economy.  Hanauer says it is “disingenuous” to attribute job creation to the wealthy when in fact it is the middle class, armed with sufficient spending power (i.e., wealth taken from the rich and redistributed), that drives up demand for products and thus creates jobs.  Creating new jobs, Hanauer points out, is the “last resort” of businesses—only when demand outpaces production capacity will a business hire new workers. 

Though roughly stated, Hanauer’s talk offers nothing very new or surprising.  Other than his partisan indictment of Republicans and non-Keynesians more generally, there is certainly nothing incendiary or even particularly provocative about his ideas.  Besides, Hanauer is an entrepreneur, not an economist, and his talk was only five minutes long.  It would be unfair, then, to impugn him for failing to point out that Americans have already cracked the code of affluence and now enjoy an abundance of it.  Tyler Cowen explains that America picked all the “low hanging fruit” in the decades following World War II.  Compared to 1950, we expend half as much labor for a gallon of milk, a third as much for a kilowatt of electricity, a quarter as much for an hour of air travel, a fifth as much for a refrigerator, a seventh for a three-pound chicken, a tenth for a home air conditioner, and a fiftieth for the cost of a coast-to-coast phone call.  We “have access to penicillin, air travel, good cheap food, the Internet and virtually all of the technical innovations that [Bill] Gates does,” Cowen observes.  We have so much affluence, in fact, that John Kenneth Galbraith complained that man’s desires were “no longer even evident to him,” and that modern Americans “needed an adman to tell them what they wanted.” 

Like Hanauer, I’m not qualified to challenge an entire school of economic thought, but let me pose this question:  If Galbraith was right and modern Americans by and large are free from poverty classically understood (though not free from the modern liberal recasting of poverty as that “new and deeper searing” that arises with “envy of his neighbor’s new car”), then what meaningful economic progress is yet to be made?  The modern economic problem, in my humble estimation, is precisely that, without continued innovation and entrepreneurial risk-taking, we would be left to conclude that the project of economic innovation and production is substantially done and that what’s left is to proceed with divvying up the loot.  That is, Hanauer seems to suggest the fact that demand is high has nothing to do with the fact of innovation and entrepreneurial risk-taking—as if there was a demand for tablet computers before Steve Jobs created the iPad.  While further prosperity is left to be had, Cowen points out, it will come only with increased investments of skill, capital, risk, and innovation.  If there is merit to Keynesian theory, certainly it reached its peak in the mid-20th century when America was flooded with supply—the “low hanging fruit” which Cowen says we’ve gotten sick on.  The need to incentivize new kinds of products and services, it seems to me, can only increase in an affluent society where the routine necessities of life—as well as a lot of really cool toys—are cheap and abundant. 

The Evangelical War on Mormonism That Wasn’t

A rather odd–or underreasoned–op-ed from Harvard prof Noah Feldman is making the rounds, that Mitt Romney’s candidacy is Mormonism’s ticket to American Protestant acceptance. That’s a very big yes and no, as we shall see:

As a deeply believing Mormon, he actually, sincerely (yes, sincerely) believes that his moral values are equivalent to those of evangelicals.

Why Prof. Feldman finds this worthy of note or the least bit puzzling is puzzling. Romney’s values are the same as American evangelicals’. Not only that, but the feeling is mutual.

As Dennis Prager writes:

“Traditional Jews and evangelical Christians have quite different theologies, but they often have virtually identical values. (That is why this Jew is so supportive of evangelicals and why evangelical Christians syndicate my radio show.)

Conservative Catholics and evangelicals differ on theology but share virtually every important value. The Founders differed on theology but rarely on values.

It is hard to identify any area of life in which Mitt Romney’s values and life differ in any way from the finest evangelical’s values and life. And with regard to electing a president, that is what matters.”

Via the internet, I’ve heard some of the stations Prager refers to, say WORL in Florida, which explicitly self-identifies as “Christian” in its station breaks. They carry the conservative Jewish commentator Michael Medved as well. They don’t mind.

In 2012 the evangelical right has embraced the American Founding’s vision of religious pluralism—park the soteriology [the business of salvation] at the door and concern yourselves politically only with the concerns of this world. This detente has been vitiated by the rise of secular-progressivism and/or libertarianism-libertinism, both of which largely reject any notion of natural law, that there exist objective and universal standards of morality that a society should govern itself by.  The “Judeo-Christian” thing.

Feldman, who is a Harvardly expert on religion as well as constitutional law, adds to the undifferentiated soupiness thus:

In historical terms, this change is business as usual. Catholics came to be seen as a legitimate Christian denomination only after years of oppression. Then came the acceptance of Jews. Mormons are the latest beneficiaries. Eventually, Muslims and Hindus will have their day as well.

Well, not exactly. It’s not just one big stew where you toss in this religion or that one, as if they’re all more or less the same. Salt isn’t pepper isn’t an onion isn’t a carrot or a hunk of lamb or even a stone.  [Stone soup actually tastes like water with it a stone in it.  Ick.]

Theologically, Christianity’s relationship with Judaism has finally warmed in the past century, that the Jews have a legitimate place in God’s plan, and it’s certainly indisputable that their Bible is biblical. However, there will be no such dispensation for the unbiblical Book of Mormon [or the Quran, for that matter].  When it comes to man’s religions, one size does not fit all.

A Rev. Frank Pastore [ex-Cincinnati Reds pitcher, now a scholar and evangelical pastor and talk show host] can support Romney socio-politically [“We’re not electing a pastor, we’re electing a president”], but has reservations that such a tolerance-acceptance is a theological endorsement of Mormonism as a legitimate variant of Christianity.

Many Christian sects remain kissin’ cousins, and accept each others’ legitimacy as authentic Christianity. But Mormonism with its additional book of revelation [like Islam]?

No can do. Never. But that’s theology.  All that stuff will be settled on Judgment Day and not one day before.

Back here on earth, for years now, the leftish chattering class has been predicting an evangelical rejection of Mitt Romney’s candidacy—and thus a splitting or neutering of the Religious Right if and when he’s nominated.

But the Religious Right are neither the blithering idiots nor the implacable theological ideologues that would reject a Romney for an Obama, whose own Christianity hasn’t much in common with theirs when it comes to this here planet. 

[Even as the president’s surrogates are “letting slip” that Barack Obama the man is theologically much more the orthodox Christian than he was in 2008. That should probably be a post of its own. I find it inappropriate—bizarre if not cynical—for one’s pastors and advisors to be leaking a candidate’s theological bona fides to the press.]

Indeed, it’s the evangelical right who have settled comfortably into the Founding era’s religious pluralism, a sort of don’t-ask-don’t-tell—that doctrine and dogma are unhelpful, and indeed are needless distractions when it comes to constructing a polity congenial to your values.

As John Adams wrote to Abigail about his cousin S[amuel] Adams—an über-Calvinist—at the very first Continental Congress in September 1774:

When the Congress first met, Mr. Cushing made a Motion, that it should be opened with Prayer. It was opposed by Mr. Jay of N. York and Mr. Rutledge of South Carolina, because we were so divided in religious Sentiments, some Episcopalians, some Quakers, some Aanabaptists, some Presbyterians and some Congregationalists, so that We could not join in the same Act of Worship.

Mr. S. Adams arose and said he was no Bigot, and could hear a Prayer from a Gentleman of Piety and Virtue, who was at the same Time a Friend to his Country.

He was a Stranger in Phyladelphia, but had heard that Mr. Duche (Dushay they pronounce it) deserved that Character, and therefore he moved that Mr. Duche, an episcopal [Anglican, i.e., Church of England—TVD] Clergyman, might be desired, to read Prayers to the Congress, tomorrow Morning.

The Motion was seconded and passed in the Affirmative.

That the Religious Right fancy themselves the successors of the American Founding is well-known. Few of them would find the above story surprising or anything less than wise: in the 21st century, the most Protestant issue joint politico-moral declarations with the most Papish

The Founders would smile if not laugh in satisfaction, and it’s very disappointing to those who oppose the Religious Right, I suppose, that they refuse to commit political suicide over theology. But it’s an American tradition that goes back to at least 1774 and the launch of the American Revolution, and that’s very good thing.

Otherwise, you know, you’d be reading this in English.

“College is not for everybody”

[Originally posted on the main page]

A caller on NPR’s Talk of the Nation offered a very interesting story about whether a college degree is a sound investment.  Note the reflexive defense from Kathleen Shea Smith, a student counselor who advocates in her earlier comments on the program that “it’s worth the investment” to get that bachelor’s degree:

ABRAHAM: Yeah, well, I was just going to talk about – this is kind of from an individual standpoint, (unintelligible) rather than like a macro standpoint. But when I was being kind of briefed about college life when I was in high school, they had all kinds of – you know, speakers would come to us and talk to us about how to prepare for college.

And they would talk to us about our future, and they would always, you know, say something along the line about how college wasn’t for everyone. But then that’s about all they ever explore into it. And I had to work fulltime to go to college, and I went to college for about two-and-a-half years before I dropped out, and my wife also dropped out.

And we found out that college was – you know, we were doing poorly because we had to work fulltime. I was working more than 40 hours a week. My wife was working about 35 to 36. And as we moved along in our service industry careers, we found that, you know, there was nothing preventing us from giving ourselves the life that we wanted without going to college.

And I feel like that’s not a very well-represented viewpoint. I feel like I was never really told that that was something that I could do. And we’ve gotten actually to the point where my wife has moved on – this is in as little as six years from an entry-level position at a clothing retailer that she was able to advance to the point where I no longer have to work.

And we’re homeowners, and we have a young son, and we have a couple of dogs, and we live in the suburbs, and it’s all very, you know, American dreamy. And I work part-time just for extra money.

CONAN: Well, congratulations. I’m really glad it worked out for you.

ABRAHAM: Well, yeah, it did work out well for me, and I understand that, you know, these things are very, very, you know, individualistic, and it’s not really, you know, necessarily very relevant from a large standpoint because, you know, obviously, we have, you know, the future to think about. We can’t just tell everybody to go work at a clothing retailer all the time.

CONAN: No, I understand. But do you have kids?

ABRAHAM: I’m sorry. What was that?

CONAN: Do you have children?

ABRAHAM: Yeah. We have one child. He was just born, and that was actually the main reason why I stopped working because…

CONAN: To take care. Yeah.

ABRAHAM: Yeah. I’m a stay-at-home dad now. I’m only working part time, and it’s great. But what I, I guess, the gist of what I’m trying to say is that I was never told that, you know, entry-level, uneducated, you know, work was something that was viable, especially since we’re in a depressed area. All the factory jobs have left town. Those are kind of what the old guard jobs were.

CONAN: Sure. Yeah. Well, good luck. And are you planning to send your son or your daughter to college?

ABRAHAM: That’s up to him.

CONAN: OK. Thanks very much for the call, Abraham.

ABRAHAM: Thank you, sir.

CONAN: And, Kathleen Shea Smith, college is not for everybody.

SMITH: It may not be, and it sounds like it worked out really well for Abraham. And I think – but if we do, again, go back to the statistics and the results [around $1,025 weekly earnings with a bachelor’s versus $625 without], it’s just the numbers are really telling as far as the benefits of college. But again, it’s an individual decision, and I know that we don’t want to impose our views on other people, but I think that the numbers really do speak to the issue.

Abraham is making a very important observation here that cannot be so cavalierly shrugged off with a few simplistic stats.  Indeed, Abraham has already anticipated Ms. Smith’s response, having described how anyone interested in long-term financial independence is given the same sales pitch—i.e., that college is the answer, and the throwaway line that “college is not for everyone” is offered merely as an empty disclaimer, not to be taken seriously by anyone who can stomach the student loan debt and opportunity cost.

Thus, the college degree group’s numbers are skewed upwards by folks like Abraham and his wife but who did stick it out the four years—i.e., people who would have been good earners with or without the degree.  Charles Murray made this very point in Real Education:

But while it is true that the average person with a BA makes more than the average person without a BA, getting a BA is still going to be the wrong economic decision for many high-school graduates. Wages within occupations form a distribution. Young people with okay-but-not-great academic ability who are thinking about whether to go after a BA need to consider the competition they will face after they graduate. Let me put these calculations in terms of a specific example, a young man who has just graduated from high school and is trying to decide whether to become an electrician or go to college and major in business, hoping to become a white-collar manager. He is at the 70th percentile in linguistic ability and logical-mathematical ability—someone who shouldn’t go to college by my standards, but who can, in today’s world, easily find a college that will give him a degree. He is exactly average in interpersonal and intrapersonal ability. He is at the 95th percentile in the small-motor skills and spatial abilities that are helpful in being a good electrician.

He begins by looking up the average income of electricians and managers on the Bureau of Labor Statistics website, and finds that the mean annual income for electricians in 2005 was $45,630, only about half of the $88,450 mean for management occupations. It looks as if getting a BA will buy him a huge wage premium. Should he try to get the BA on economic grounds?

To make his decision correctly, our young man must start by throwing out the averages. He has the ability to become an excellent electrician and can reasonably expect to be near the top of the electricians’ income distribution. He does not have it in him to be an excellent manager, because he is only average in interpersonal and intrapersonal ability and only modestly above average in academic ability, all of which are important for becoming a good manager, while his competitors for those slots will include many who are high in all of those abilities. Realistically, he should be looking at the incomes toward the bottom of the distribution of managers. With that in mind, he goes back to the Bureau of Labor Statistics website and discovers that an electrician at the 90th percentile of electricians’ incomes made $70,480 in 2005, almost twice the income of a manager at the 10th percentile of managers’ incomes ($37,800). Even if our young man successfully completes college and gets a BA (which is far from certain), he is likely to make less money than if he becomes an electrician.

. . . .

What I have said of electricians is true throughout the American job market. The income for the top people in a wide variety of occupations that do not require a college degree is higher than the average income for many occupations that require a BA. Furthermore, the range and number of such jobs is expanding rapidly. The need for assembly-line workers in factories (one of the most boring jobs ever invented) is falling, but the demand for skilled technicians of every kind—in health care, information technology, transportation networks, and every other industry that relies on high-tech equipment—is expanding. The service sector includes many low-skill, low-paying jobs, but it also includes growing numbers of specialized jobs that pay well (for example, in health care and the entertainment and leisure industries). Construction offers an array of high-paying jobs for people who are good at what they do. It’s not just skilled labor in the standard construction trades that is in high demand. The increase in wealth in American society has increased the demand for all sorts of craftsmanship. . . . There has never been a time in history when people with skills not taught in college have been in so much demand at such high pay as today, nor a time when the range of such jobs has been so wide. In today’s America, finding a first-rate lawyer or physician is easy. Finding first-rate skilled labor is hard.

[N.B.  Murray’s analysis, published in August 2008, suggesting that finding any kind of employment is "easy" was almost certainly based on pre-recession circumstances.]

This is not meant to discourage education by any means.  Like Murray, I agree with John Stuart Mill’s sentiment that “Universities are not intended to teach the knowledge required to fit men for some special mode of gaining their livelihood. Their object is not to make skilful lawyers, or physicians, or engineers, but capable and cultivated human beings.”  However, when 90% of high school seniors expect to go to college and 70% expect to work in professional jobs, the trends of defeated expectations and crushing student debts are bound to continue.  Citing statistics about the average comparative incomes of college graduates versus non-graduates, without more, does a disservice to clear thinking on this issue.

Libertarianism in a Nutshell

I fancy meself a South Park Republican, no prig he, more likely to laugh at the ineptness of somebody trying to offend him than to be offended. A Piss Christ or a Virgin Mary made of elephant shit is so last century it’s hardly worth the bother of feigning outrage.

But I do confess that our friends and allies in Japan have come up with something I’m compelled/appalled enough to hide behind a link.

The only consolation is that there’s really nothing to be done for an encore.

Presuppositional Constitutionalism

coin-in-god-we-trustDoes the Constitution assume certain presuppositions on the part of those it means to govern?  If so, what are those presuppositions? 

I submit the answer to the first question is yes, and explain the presuppositions that by necessity must be true for our Constitution to be intelligible. 

In light of the project begun here recently to explore the contemporary significance of the natural law, I  offer for your consideration my theory of natural law constitutionalism, or “presuppositional constitutionalism.”   It is largely based on Hadley Arkes’s theory set out in his 1986 book, First Things.  The theory, in short, is as follows:  Natural law and constitutionalism are each concerned with transcendental propositions that make their respective projects intelligible.  The U.S. Constitution, for example, does not state that its provisions are to be construed to avoid contradictions.  Nor does it anywhere use the word “unconstitutional.”  Yet, it does not give us any pause that, without any express guidance in the text of the Constitution, certain rules of logical and linguistic construction are applied to the Constitution, and that hundreds of laws have been struck down as “unconstitutional” without any express mechanism for doing so.  Why does this not concern us?  Because it would be absurd to presume that reasonable rules of construction would not be applied, or that a law that contradicts our Constitution could be anything other than unconstitutional.  These truths are implicit in logic.  To deny them would be the height of foolishness. 

I submit that there is a trove of such truths, preconditions I call them, that are found “under the hood” of the Constitution.  Each of them are necessary to making the document intelligible, and each of them would be utterly foolish to deny.  That is, denying them would render us incapable of giving an account for our knowledge about the world and would otherwise undermine our essence as human beings.  

This take on natural law reasoning is a little different than what is commonly advanced.  Yes, it still begins with an acknowledgement of the sort of being man is, holding this, his nature, as the touchstone for moral reasoning.  Based on certain notions about who man is and the sorts of things he was made for, we can engage in some reasoning about how his relationships ought to be ordered, how he should comport himself, what his rights and obligations are, and so on.  I’ve always had a great deal of sympathy for the project, and as to certain questions, I think it can often be compelling.  But I have never felt the teleology-centric approach captures its true force. 

To my thinking, many natural lawyers skip an enormously profitable theoretical step at the beginning of the inquiry.  That step is to acknowledge, as a presuppositional (a priori) matter, that it is man’s nature is to acquire knowledge.  Man, at his core, is a philosopher, an insatiable seeker of truth about his reality.  Truth and knowledge are related but different concepts that drive man’s reasoning and lead us to necessarily accept certain claims about reality and reject others.  Recall Descartes’ extreme critical reasoning exercise of casting himself in total self-doubt, disqualifying all information acquired through his senses.  This ultimate skepticism is the extreme form of man’s search for truth.  We cannot be sure that our senses do not betray us, or that what we call reality is not some elaborate dream, or that we are not in the Matrix.  If truth were man’s sole directive, we might still be mired in Cartesian doubt with nothing to show for the human project but the cogito

But truth is not man’s sole directive.  He also insists that he must know what can reasonably be known about his reality.  If he is to know anything about his reality, he must presuppose certain truths.  One will immediately detect a tension between truth and knowledge, as it would appear the project for establishing truth is to be compromised for the sake of the knowledge project.  Recall, however, that the truth project has never been advanced past the point of solipsism.  Man is thus left with this choice:  Accept that you may have knowledge of reality on the basis of reasonable presuppositions, or else accept that you may have no knowledge at all.  Given our nature as beings who crave to understand reality, the latter choice is the very definition of absurd.

On this point, Immanuel Kant gave the following answer to David Hume who, because of his atheism, was unable to escape the solipsism of Cartesian doubt and satisfy himself that there was any rational justification for a belief in causation:  “it is under this supposition only [i.e., the supposition that a rule of causation exists] that an experience of anything that happens becomes possible.”  The transcendental nature of causation as a rule is “the foundation of all experience, and consequently preceded it a priori.”  In other words, unless we are prepared to forfeit the possibility of knowledge about any experience whatsoever, causation must be true. 

Thomas Paine touched on a similar sentiment of transcendental political rules in his Dissertation on First Principles of Government: “Every art and science has some point or alphabet at which the study of that art or science begins and by the assistance of which the progress is facilitated. The same method ought to be observed with respect to the science of government.”  If we are to make anything in the science of politics intelligible, we must admit certain presuppositions that give rise to intelligibility.  Otherwise, we will effectively be mired in a dark age of political knowledge with no common ground on which to advance our project. 

To put it more simply, there are certain facts about the world that must be true.  Not because we can see or measure them—information acquired through our senses does not rise to the level of logical necessity.  There is no empirical fact that must be true.  As Thomas Reid observed, “Experience informs us only of what is, or has been, not of what must be.”  Indeed, we have already established we have reason to doubt those “facts” which we can know only by our senses.  Instead, these facts I am referring to must be true because, were they not, we would be cast into absolute solipsism and will have lost all connection with the world and with our fellow man.  In the philosophical sense, the person who rejects such truths is made a fool: he is unable to account for his reality, his relationships, indeed his very nature. 

Consider the common logical proof, “All men are mortal; Socrates is a man; thus, Socrates is mortal.”  The argument is both sound and valid, and its conclusion true.  Presumably, however, you are still free to reject it.  Moral and logical laws are not self-enforcing like physical laws are.  This observation prompted Robert Nozick to muse:  “Wouldn’t it be better if philosophical arguments left the person no possible answer at all, reducing him to impotent silence? Even then, he might sit there silently, smiling, Buddhalike. Perhaps philosophers need arguments so powerful they set up reverberations in the brain: if the person refuses to accept the conclusion, he dies. How’s that for a powerful argument?”

However, it would be wrong to suggest that rejecting the simple argument above would carry no consequences.  Observing that the premises are true and the form of the argument is sound, only a degenerate fool would reject the conclusion.  Again acknowledging that man’s nature is to acquire truth and knowledge about the world, we would rightly conclude such a person is, in a teleological sense (i.e., with respect to the sort of being he is and what he is made for), defective.  

Natural reasoning, then, begins with the project of ascertaining those facts about reality that must be true in order to get the knowledge project off the ground.  This is not to say that we can stipulate such facts arbitrarily.  This is where religion and metaphysics come into play to provide a coherent set of transcendental facts.  Which religion or metaphysical theory is most appealing can be left to the individual as far as the natural reasoning project goes.  However, it should provide a basis for overcoming the solipsism of Cartesian doubt, it should account for the existence of laws by establishing order in our reality, it should account for the existence of immaterial things such as numbers and grammar and the laws of logic, it should account for the reliability of our senses, and so on. 

(It should be observed that not all worldviews are created equal.  In the absence of religion or some other systematic way of developing a worldview, the project of giving an account of the necessary preconditions for intelligibility of reality may justifiably attract a host of criticisms.  Elsewhere, I have accused some atheists of engaging in “shopping cart epistemology,” positing what they need to be true about the world when the need arises, thus rendering their worldview ad hoc and arbitrary.  Hadley Arkes observes something similar, but ultimately concludes that, with respect to the natural law project, it is acceptable to posit that which is needed to make reality intelligible.  “[T]o say that we ‘assume’ or presuppose the existence of time [for example] is not to say that we indulge an arbitrary assumption whose truth cannot be known. It is to recognize, rather, that we are dealing with a necessary truth or first principle whose understanding provides the foundation for the understanding of all other things.”)

A persistent problem for natural lawyers has been the reluctance of skeptics to concede the existence of an objective morality.  It should be clear by now, however, that the empirical model itself has already forced the skeptic to concede the existence of certain non-empirical, presuppositional truths.  Now that we have established the necessity of truths that do not depend for their validity on experience or feelings or a consensus, the skeptic has no ground to deny the existence of morals.  That is, the skeptic acknowledges the existence of transcendental presuppositions to acquire one kind of knowledge.  The skeptic cannot arbitrarily deny the existence of other presuppositions to acquire a different kind of knowledge, moral knowledge, which is equally important to man’s understanding of his reality. 

With this in mind, we can begin to understand why certain political principle facts must be objectively true.  That all men are created equal is one such principle.  I must assume all men are of the same nature as I am.  Otherwise, I would have no intelligible basis for moral objection or approval of the actions of another.  I would have no intelligible basis for purporting to communicate or transact or reason with others.  It is only by assuming that others are of the same nature as I am that I can intelligibly and reasonably enter into relationships with them.  If I do not assume this fact, all my social interactions are betrayed and irrational and meaningless—I may as well be talking to a plant or a bar of soap or any other thing that is not of a nature equal to my own.  It is thus a transcendental necessity, a presuppositional fact about the world, that all men are created equal. 

Similarly, as Hadley Arkes observed, “acting morally is bound up with the exercise of giving reasons. And by ‘giving reasons,’ of course, we would not mean merely reporting on one’s motives (‘I hit him because I felt the need for excitement’), but offering justifications.”  Again, man cannot reject his essential nature as a moral being without conceding the possibility of making any moral judgments about the world, e.g., that murder and rape and genocide are evil, and that courage and charity and selflessness are praiseworthy. 

Property is established under a similar analysis.  Man must find what he needs for sustenance and flourishing in nature, and thus is of central importance to his worldview constructed through reason.  At the outset, then, we cannot say that man is presuppositionally neutral in this respect.  Man necessarily has some natural, pre-empirical relationship with property. 

Based on what we have already seen, we can begin to understand what that relationship is.  If all men are qualitatively equal, then no one man can impinge on another’s reasonable actions without justification.  Man need not give any account to any other for growing, gathering, catching, or producing the necessities of his life and flourishing so long as his activity does not impinge on another’s ability to do the same.  Inversely, man must gain consent or offer reasons amounting to a justification before taking the property of another.  A principle (if it could be called that) of “might makes right” would lay waste to man’s precommitment to reason and reason’s injunction not to act arbitrarily.  Natural physical strength is, as far as man is concerned, arbitrary and thus cannot in reason provide a justification for altering relationships between man and property. 

As a starting point, then, we may conclude that man has a natural right to private property.  This does not mean that we cannot enter into compacts by which we agree to pool our resources for a common or greater good.  Nor does it necessarily mean that a majority’s will could not justify the taking of an individual’s property for a greater good.  But even such a system conceptually begins with an acknowledgement of an individual right to property—the justification offered must outweigh the individual’s claim.  This analysis deserves its own post, so I do not attempt any further treatment here. 

Liberty is also a necessary presupposition to intelligibility of any political reality.  The fact of man’s essential moral nature carries the germ that hatches the idea of liberty.  Hadley Arkes set this out nicely with respect to  natural law’s injunction against racial discrimination, but the analysis also applies to liberty generally:

[T]he language of morals makes no sense when it is directed toward acts that are determined by the causal laws of nature. We could never sensibly say that the earth is obliged to revolve about the sun, and that it would be wrong—or worthy of blame—if it did not. The language of morals must presuppose, of necessity a being who is free to choose one course of action or another. It is only because that being is free that he can be held responsible for his acts, and that he may, with coherence, be blamed or praised. When people are rewarded or punished not for their own acts, but for the accident of their racial background, they are not praised or blamed for anything that it was in their power to affect, and they are treated, therefore, as though they did not in fact possess the freedom or autonomy of moral agents. They are treated as though their acts were determined by causal laws beyond their own governance. As we shall see, then, the wrongness of this racial discrimination is rooted in the very logic of morals, and therefore it must be said that racial discrimination is wrong of necessity.”

Likewise with respect to liberty, if man is not free to choose, he is denied the exercise of his essential moral nature.  The political guarantee of individual liberty, therefore, necessarily follows from natural law reasoning such that to deny it defeats his nature. 

We begin to see how natural law reasoning forms the basis of constitutionalism, particularly American constitutionalism. 

If you have read this very long post to this point, let me now offer why I think this sort of analysis is so important.  It has been submitted by others on this blog that political positions and principles are essentially nothing more than “ideology,” or “my team vs. your team” that are hopelessly partisan and ultimately matters of personal taste.  And we tend to float along with this mindset so long as we don’t feel too strongly about our disagreements.  But what happens when we do?  It is important that we explore what we mean by things like rights and moral reasoning.  We are not all just floating past one other on separate islands.  We share a common nature, and common faculties.  Some of our ideas comport with our nature and faculties, and others do not.  It is my firm belief that we can more effectively vet those ideas than we often do. 

I welcome your comments. 

[Cross-posted at the main page]

America, Religious Freedom, and the Natural Law

A recent George Weigel commencement address.

Defending Religious Freedom in Full: A Generation’s Challenge

“[A] special word of thanks, today, to the parents of today’s graduates — and the grandparents, and the other family members — who have helped bring you, the Class of 2012, to this pivotal moment in your lives.

natural lawyerToday is, by its nature — and I think at Benedictine College we can still speak of the “nature” of things! — a day of celebration, a day of remembrance, and a day of thanksgiving.

We share, today, a unique and critical moment in the history of the Catholic Church in the United States. At the time of the American Revolution, Catholics accounted for less than one per cent of the population of the thirteen colonies — a tiny population clustered primarily in my native Maryland and a few Pennsylvania counties. Yet within a few decades of the Founding, the great tides of European immigration that began to wash onto the shores of the new nation – those “huddled masses yearning to breathe free,” as they are memorialized on the Statue of Liberty — brought millions of Catholics to the New World: at first, Irish and Germans; later, Italians, Poles, Czechs, Slovaks, Ruthenians, and the many others who wove their lives, their traditions, and their aspirations into the rich tapestry of American democracy. Those 19th century immigrants felt the sting of anti-Catholic prejudice, even anti-Catholic violence. But notwithstanding that bigotry, Catholics have, I believe, almost always felt at home in these United States.

We have felt at home because we have thrived here; with the exception of immigrant Jews, no religious group has prospered more in America than the Catholic community. Yet Catholic “at-homeness” in the United States has had a deeper philosophical and moral texture. One of the great Catholic students of American democracy, Father John Courtney Murray, described that side of the Catholic experience of America in these terms, in We Hold These Truths: Catholic Reflections on the American Proposition, a book published fifty-two years ago:

In this second decade of the third millennium, there are many grave questions be debated in America: the question of the legal protection of innocent human life from conception until natural death; the question of long-term strategy and morally worthy tactics in the war against Islamist jihadism; the question of how we attend to the sick and how we manage immigration; the question of fitting public policy ends to fiscal means; the question of building an appropriate regulatory structure around the biotech revolution so that the new genetic knowledge leads to genuine human flourishing rather than to a stunted and manufactured humanity; the question of the health of American civil society and of the American national character; the list goes on and on. The very question of what should be on “the public policy agenda,” and what ought to be left to the private and independent sectors, is being as vigorously contested in our country today as at any time since the Great Depression and the New Deal. Yet amidst all this churning, the gravest question for our public culture is whether what Father Murray called the “American consensus” — that ensemble of “ethical and political principles drawn from the tradition of natural law” — still holds.

There are reasons to be concerned.

In October 2009, the nation’s political newspaper of record, the Washington Post, ran an editorial condemning what it termed the “extremist views” of a candidate for attorney general of Virginia who had suggested that the natural moral law was still a useful guide to public policy. The Post, determined to nail down the claim that homosexual orientation is the equivalent of race for purposes of U.S. civil rights law, deplored this as “a retrofit [of] the old language of racism, bias, and intolerance in a new context.” Yet the Post’s own claim was, to adopt its language, “extremist.” For it suggested that the label “bigot” ought to be applied to notable historical personalities who had appealed to the natural moral law in causes the Post would presumably regard as admirable: figures such as Thomas Jefferson, staking America’s claim to independent nationhood on “self-evident” moral truths derived from “the laws of nature”; or Martin Luther King, Jr., arguing in his Letter from Birmingham Jail that “an unjust law is a human law that is not rooted in eternal law and natural law”; or Pope John Paul II, who, at the United Nations in 1995, suggested that the truths of the natural moral law — “the moral logic which is built into human life,” as he put it — could serve as a universal “grammar” enabling cross-cultural dialogue.

Appeals to the natural moral law we can know by reason underwrote the American civil rights revolution. Appeals to that same natural moral law underwrite the pro-life movement, the successor to the civil rights movement. And appeals to the natural moral law have underwritten U.S. international human rights policy for the past thirty years. Until, that is, December 2009, when the Secretary of State of the United States, in a speech at Georgetown University, emptied the concept of religious freedom of everything save the “freedom to worship” while asserting, in a catalogue of what she claimed were fundamental international human rights, that people “must be free…to love in the way they choose” — which “choice” must, presumably, be protected by international human rights covenants and national and local civil rights laws.

This speech, as things turned out, was one harbinger of an assault on religious freedom that continues to this day — an assault that imagines “religious freedom” to be a kind of “privacy right” to certain leisure-time activities, but nothing more than that. This dramatic misconception of religious freedom was evident in the present administration’s attempt to re-write federal employment law by dissolving the “ministerial exemption” that had long protected the integrity of religious institutions. It was evident in the administration’s refusal to continue funding the U.S. bishops’ efforts to help women who had been victims of sex-trafficking (because the Church refused to provide abortion as part of that work). And it has been most dramatically evident in the January HHS mandate that requires all employers (including religious institutions with moral objections and private-sector employers with religiously-informed moral objections) to facilitate the provision of contraceptives, sterilizations, and abortifacient drugs like Plan B and Ella to their employees.

All of this suggests that one of the great challenges of your generation, my fellow-members of the Class of 2012 of Benedictine College, will be to rise to the defense of religious freedom in full. And, indeed, what could be a more apt challenge for the graduates of a college named in honor of the saint whose inspired vision and evangelical vision saved the civilization of the classical world when it was in danger of being lost? What better challenge for the graduates of Benedictine College, named for one of the patrons of Europe, whose life-work saved the West as a civilizational enterprise built from the fruitful interaction of Jerusalem, Athens, and Rome?

For the defense of religious freedom in full which you must mount must be both cultural — in the sense of arguments winsomely and persuasively made — and political, in that you must drive the sharp edge of truth into the sometimes hard soil of public policy.

What is this “religious freedom in full” that you must defend and advance?

It surely includes freedom of worship, but it must include more than that; the Kingdom of Saudi Arabia is content with freedom of worship, so long as the Christian worship in question takes place behind closed doors in the American embassy compound in Riyadh. Religious conviction is community-forming, and communities formed by religious conviction must be free, as communities and not simply as individuals, to make arguments and bring influence to bear in public life. If religiously informed moral argument is banned from the American public square, then the public square has become, not only naked, but undemocratic and intolerant. If, on the other hand, religiously informed moral argument is welcome in public life, then we have the possibility of rebuilding, not a sacred public square (a goal the Catholic Church rejected at the Second Vatican Council), but a civil public square, in which tolerance is rightly understood as differences engaged within a bond of civility formed by a mutual commitment to reason.

It is a matter of both political common sense and democratic etiquette that Catholics in public life should make our arguments in ways that our fellow-citizens, who may not share our theological premises, can engage and understand — which is to say, in our particular case, that Catholics should bring to bear in public life the moral truths we hold through arguments framed by the grammar and vocabulary of the natural moral law. That is what John Paul II did at the United Nations in 1979 and 1995. That is what Benedict XVI did at the in 2008 and in the German Bundestag in 2011. That is what the bishops of the United States, and lay Catholics in their millions, have done over the past four decades in defense of life. And if there are some who consider such appeals to the natural moral law a form of tarted-up bigotry, well, we shall simply have to inform them, politely but firmly, that they are mistaken, and then demonstrate why.

Religious freedom in full also means that communities of religious conviction and conscience must be free to conduct the works of charity in ways that reflect their conscientious convictions. This is neither the time nor the place to discuss the problems that have been posed by tying so much of Catholic social service work and Catholic health care to government funding — save, perhaps, to note that these problems did not exist before the Supreme Court erected a spurious “right to abortion” as the right-that-trumps-all-other-rights, and before courts and legislatures decided that it was within the state’s competence to redefine marriage and to compel others to accept that redefinition through the use of coercive state power. What can be said in this context, and what must be said, is that the rights of Catholic physicians, nurses, and other health care professionals are not second-class rights that can be trumped by other rights-claims; and any state that fails to acknowledge those rights of conscience has done grave damage to religious freedom rightly understood. The same can and must be said about any state that drives the Catholic Church out of certain forms of social service because the Church refuses to concede that the state has the competence to declare as “marriage” relationships that are manifestly not marriages.

My fellow-graduates, your defense of religious freedom is going to require the skills of reasoning and argument that you acquired here at Benedictine College. It is going to require that some of you accept the risk and challenge of public service in elective office. And it going to require all of you to support those who take, as their vocation, the defense and promotion of religious freedom in full.

This will be the work of a lifetime. But it must begin sooner rather than later, for the threats to religious freedom among us are great, and many of them are deeply embedded in postmodern American culture. This work will not be without cost. Some of you may suffer various forms of martyrdom in taking up this cause: the martyrdom of ridicule, of being labeled “intolerant” and “bigoted”; the martyrdom of career paths blocked and promotions denied because of your adherence to the moral truth of things; the martyrdom of political defeat, or a judicial case well-argued but lost. Fidelity to the truth can have its costs. Yet as Blessed John Paul II taught young people all over the world, those costs are worth paying because the truth sets us free in the deepest sense of human liberation. Thomas More, patron saint of Catholics in public life, was never more a free man than when he bent his neck to the executioner’s axe in free adherence to the truth.

Let us pray that it does not come to that for any of you, or indeed for any of us. But let us also be clear on the stakes for which your generation is playing, which are nothing less than the long-term integrity of American democracy. So: be the culture-forming heirs of St. Benedict that your education here has prepared you to be. Be the champions of religious freedom in full. In doing that, you will give America a new birth of freedom — freedom tethered to truth and ordered to goodness, freedom that sets us free in the noblest sense of human liberation.

Godspeed on your journey.

Delivered May 12, 2012 at Benedictine College, Atchison, Kansas.

Stimulus first, austerity later

Geezer-Race-300x231.jpgVia Alex Tabarrok, a recent study by Richard Evans, Laurence Kotiloff, and Kerk Philips at VoxEU examines the effects of long-term large-scale redistribution of young Americans’ savings to the elderly:

[T]he young, because they have longer remaining lifespans than the old, have much lower propensities to consume out of their remaining lifetime resources. This prediction is strongly confirmed for the US by Gokhale et al (1996).

Hence, in taking from young savers and giving to old spenders, which Uncle Sam has spent six decades doing on a massive scale, the lifecycle model predicts a major decline in US net national saving associated with a major rise in the absolute and relative consumption of the elderly. This is precisely what the data show.

In 1965, the US net national saving was 15.6% of net national income. Last year, it was just 0.9%. And, according to Gokhale et al (1996) and Lee and Mason (2012), the secular demise in US saving has coincided with a spectacular rise in the consumption of older Americans relative to that of younger Americans.

As Feldstein and Horioka (1980) document, US net domestic saving tracks US net national saving. Hence, postwar intergenerational redistribution has not only lowered net national saving; it has also reduced net domestic investment, from 14.0% of national income in 1965 to just 3.6% in 2011. This decline in the rate of net domestic investment is, no doubt, playing a major role in the slow growth in US wages. Indeed, the level of private-sector average real earnings per hour, exclusive of fringe benefits, is lower today than it was 40 years ago.

Kevin Drum objects that the VoxEU study comes off as overly pessimistic.  The study reports that simulations suggest that massive young-to-old redistributions take on average a century to reach 100% confiscation.  To which Drum demurs: “Say what?” 

Putting aside economic predictions of when it will be “game over,” it can hardly be denied that our present course is headed to ruin.  We cannot expect the young to save and invest given existing structural political incentives to let the government worry about the future for you.  “Stimulus now, austerity later” is a fine mantra if you can believe austerity will ever come.  But our leaders have given us little reason to think so.   As Garrett Jones puts it, “the best way to prove you’ll do something later is to do it now.”  “Once your politicians have built a good reputation, you can do quantitative easing without setting off inflation, you can run massive deficits without scaring bondholders.  But reputations get spent.”  Like the budget, Washington’s credibility has long been running a deficit for some time. 

The game, then, is finding new ways of pushing austerity out into the indeterminate future without looking like it’s because you’re unwilling to endure the harshness of fiscal reality.  Just say, like Drum does, that we’re too reliant on foreign oil and we need to invest in renewable energy before we think about austerity.  And education.  And healthcare.  And pensions.  Just fix all that, then we’ll be austere.  Promise.

It doesn’t take an economist to see this is the camel following its nose into the tent.  Private decisions regarding spending and investing play a large role in whether banks lend, whether new businesses will begin and existing ones expand, whether new jobs will be created and employees’ compensation increased, and so on.  Programs like social security that distort underlying private decisions upset the entire ecosystem.  They warp incentives and deprive the marketplace of accurate signals.  This in turn warps the predicates:  frozen lending systems and stalled job markets are wrongly labeled “market failure” and subjected to new government programs. 

The issue ultimately is one of a house divided.  Can free market principles co-exist with planned economy aspirations?  I don’t think we have to be all one thing or all the other, but we have to be presumptively one thing or the other. 

[Cross-posted at the main page]

The Supreme Court We Deserve

imageIn one of his questions during oral arguments on the Affordable Care Act, Justice Kennedy observed the judicial presumption in favor of the constitutionality of federal statutes.  The presumption is a nod to the democratic process, which itself is generally the most decisive proxy we have for institutional legitimacy.  But it is not the proxy.  If it were, no review of “duly constituted and passed” laws would ever be necessary.  The Court review of even democratically passed laws insulates us from democratic tyranny—from majorities stripping the rights of the minority, or, in a fit of imprudence, trading inalienable rights for fashionable government services.  But the Court’s presumption in favor of constitutionality is not designed to root its decisions in legitimacy.  Rather, it aims to give its decisions the perception of legitimacy irrespective of whether those decisions are actually legitimate. 

Assuming the Court actually thinks this way (and based on the President’s recent remarks, there is reason to believe it does, at least to some extent), would upholding the Affordable Care Act increase or decrease Americans’ perception of the Court’s legitimacy?  I conclude the latter, and thus that the Court’s institutional incentives inclines it toward finding the Act unconstitutional. 

First, a few more thoughts about judicial legitimacy.  Why does the Court err on the side of perceived legitimacy rather than training its focus on actual legitimacy?  For one thing, the Court does not have special access to such things.  Judging is often hard, and if it comes to the wrong answer, better that it was first made by another branch of government closer to the people and thus the source of perceived legitimacy.  More importantly, the Court, like government generally, is a self-preserving institution.  Institutions derive no benefit by virtue of being actually “legitimate” or “right” or “just.”  They benefit from being perceived as those things, as citizens are more likely to accept its decisions.  Thus, there is no incentive inherent in the nature of the Court itself to arrive at actually legitimate results. 

imageThis is not to say that the human beings acting as judges have no incentive to reach actually legitimate results.  But for the Court as an institution, the only incentive is to get the result that will be perceived as legitimate, either immediately or at some point in the not-too-distant future.  (Because of its conservative nature and insulation from politics, the Court is permitted a much longer time horizon in this regard.  Thus, it may be to the Court’s advantage to hand down a ruling that may be unpopular in the short term, but that will make the Court appear prescient and worthy of trust in the long term.)

In short, the Court’s institutional incentives include perceived short-term legitimacy and perceived long-term legitimacy.  The only other possible motivation (excluding bad faith) is judges’ personal incentive to achieve actual legitimacy, whether in the individual decision, or in the justice system more broadly, or in society even more broadly.   Mileage may vary as to whether and to what extent these translate into perceived legitimacy. 

This may seem a cynical, nihilistic way of looking at the Court, but really it’s not.  By concerning itself with the perception of legitimacy, the Court must look to the views and deeply held beliefs of society.  These beliefs thus may form the basis for the Court’s decisions.  That is not to say the Court ought to pander to those beliefs merely to boost its legitimacy index.  But to the extent those beliefs are not internally self-contradictory (e.g., slavery versus the deeply held belief in individual liberty), it is appropriate for the Court to consider them. 

To maximize its perceived legitimacy, the Court must do more than reach a certain result.  Because of the nature of judicial power, the process and analysis that goes into reaching the result also count for a lot.  Thus, a professional, intellectual, and experienced Court may be able to achieve greater perceived legitimacy than one that is less so.  However, because the Court is primarily concerned with perceived legitimacy, intellectual rigor will take the Court only so far.  One can imagine brilliant judicial decisions written in what, to lay persons, might amount to a different language.  Decisions whose philosophical brilliance render them indecipherable to the public will count for little. 

The possible outcomes of the Affordable Care Act illustrate the point.  If, in upholding the individual mandate, the decision is too intellectually ambitious and convoluted, the Court may be perceived as having used philosophical abstractions to avoid its duty to review an unprecedented overstep of the federal government’s limited and enumerated power.  But if, in finding the individual mandate violates the Constitution, the decision is not ambitious and creative enough, the Court may be perceived as having feigned ignorance in order to deal a partisan blow to a sitting president’s signature domestic policy achievement. 

If it were somehow possible to rate the sophistication of judicial reasoning, we might insist that the Court’s decisions clock in at a certain level, say, a 5 on a scale of 1 to 10.  We might conclude that decisions rating below 5 are conspicuously incurious, and that ratings above 5 are conspicuously overzealous.  In either case, differing degrees of sophistication of judicial reasoning suggests the Court may be using just the right degree in a given case to reach a particular conclusion.  Observers would rightly conclude this is illegitimate.  In reality, of course, there is no such scale to rate the sophistication of judicial opinions.  Nonetheless, we can discuss whether creative rationales like those offered by Professor Jack Balkin would, if adopted by the Court, evidence conclusion-oriented reasoning. 

On the other hand, sophisticated or convoluted judicial decisions do not necessarily suggest a conclusion-oriented Court. There are three ways to explain a convoluted decision.  First, it is simply a hard case, and thus an intricate analysis itself is necessary to achieve perceived legitimacy.  In other words, the analysis itself is the basis of the perceived legitimacy.  This frequently happens in review of technocratic agency actions where the outcome itself often does not have much impact on the average citizen.  One might criticize agencies on the basis that they result in many convoluted court decisions, thereby undermining the perceived legitimacy both of the Court and the agencies. 

Second, the outcome that will be perceived as the most legitimate requires a convoluted analysis to get there.  In other words, the outcome is the basis of the perceived legitimacy.  This assumes that legitimacy is perceived principally in the outcome, or at least that the convolution will not significantly undermine that perception.  Whether the perceived legitimacy is to come in the short- or long-term is a judgment call the court must make. 

The third possible explanation for convoluted court opinions is that the Court is convinced in the objective rightness of the outcome.  Dred Scott v. Sandford and Roe v. Wade are examples; it can hardly be argued that the Court could have reasonably presumed either decision would elevate its esteem.  Relatedly, the Court may be convinced that the outcome, either despite of or in addition to its being objectively right, is necessary to the preservation of the state and thus the Court itself.  Brown v. Board is an example. 

All things being equal, then, it is in the Court’s interest—the interest of being perceived as legitimate—to avoid convoluted analyses whenever possible. 

Consider again the Court’s possible approach to the Affordable Care Act.  Even now, more than two years after the Act was passed, it fails to garner a majority of public support.  Thus, the Court is not likely to gain any perceived legitimacy in the short term by upholding it.  The longer term obviously is harder to predict, but certainly the Court could be perceived as having bent to pressure from the President, who dared the Court to strike down the Act just days after oral arguments.  In order to uphold the Act, the Court would have to engage in a somewhat convoluted and unprecedented analysis, or rely on New Deal-era precedent, itself at a nadir of perceived legitimacy. 

The only basis left to uphold the Act is if the Court concludes it is objectively legitimate.  This is a hard case to make for the individual mandate.  At best, it is an instrumental good in the sense that it helps overcome the moral hazard created by another federal mandate that health providers provide emergency services to uninsured patients.  It also still presupposes a terribly inefficient health care system in which tax incentives cause most health insurance to be tethered to employment.  A stronger case perhaps could be made that upholding health care legislation creating a universal single-payer system would be objectively legitimate.  It probably is not unfair to say that the individual mandate is something of a necessary evil in the service of an arguably objectively legitimate end of broadly accessible health coverage.  But it is hard to characterize it as objectively legitimate in its own right. 

Note that objective legitimacy has nothing necessarily to do with whether the decision comports with the text of the constitution, or with any other theory of judicial interpretation for that matter.  This is simply to be factored into the analysis of whether it is perceived as legitimate.  A population who doesn’t give a whit about constitutional fidelity will likely find its courts likewise caring very little.  Indeed, a population that cannot be bothered to care much about theories of constitutional construction, or consistency in constitutional construction, will have little basis on which to judge the legitimacy of judicial decisions. 

This may be why the President feels he can impact the outcome of Court’s decision, calling it “not an abstract argument” and “not even a close case.”  In fact, the “abstract arguments” have already been made in prior cases handed down during the New Deal, which have continuing legitimacy problems due to FDR’s court-packing scheme leading to “the switch in time that saved nine.”  Wickard v. Filburn, the prior case that the President was likely referring to in his recent comments, itself should not have been a close case, so out of step was it with the Commerce Clause and precedent at the time of publication.  Yet, through legal abstractions and convolutions, it provides cover for federal legislation touching on any activity that, under the “aggregation principle,” affects interstate commerce. 

If we don’t care about fidelity to the Constitution and legal processes, the Court won’t, either.  If we send the message to the Court that we will cease to regard it as legitimate if it does not simply rubber stamp popular legislation, or stamp out unpopular legislation, then over time, the Court, by operation of its institutional incentives, will have no choice but to respond to the signals of an intellectually shallow public.

This would be a decline of American politics.  It would mark the end of the studious and faithful adherence to a logical and consistent continuum in the development of law.  It would usher in the flippant selection among various and disparate bodies of disjointed legal precedent to deliver the result demanded by impatient and intellectually unserious consumers of government services.  A public who is taken in by the President’s partisan catcalling of his coequal branch of government has no right to demand better of judicial decisions. 

Can a nudist resort’s no-kids policy survive California’s civil rights law?

That’s the question asked in the lawsuit I filed recently, which has been attracting a lot of local media attention.  As the complaint alleges, my clients, owners of Desert Sun Resort in Palm Springs, were threatened with legal action under California’s Unruh Civil Rights Act unless they reversed the resort’s no-kids policy.  My clients are seeking declaratory relief that the no-kids policy is lawful. 

KNX 1070 ran this piece on the lawsuit yesterday.  Tim Conway Jr. talked about the story last night (starting at about the 34:10 mark).  Palm Spring’s local paper also ran a piece on the lawsuit yesterday, as did Valley News.  The OC Weekly’s blog had a piece up on March 23 (NSFW).

UPDATE [3/29/12]: I was on with Tim Conway, Jr. last night at 8:00 talking about the story.